Nietzsche
Full Title: Nietzsche: A Philosophical Biography
Author / Editor: Rudiger Safranski
Publisher: W.W. Norton & Company, 2001
Review © Metapsychology Vol. 6, No. 43
Reviewer: Costica Bradatan
Those readers who will
expect to come across the “true story” of Nietzsche’s life in this book will be
soon disappointed. It is true, Safranski’s work is subtitled A Philosophical Biography, but in
reality this only means that his book is “philosophical” and speculative to a
high degree and only to a limited extent “biographical” and historical. More
precisely, Safranski deals almost exclusively with those facts, events, and
encounters in Nietzsche’s life that decisively transcend their strict factual
importance, having instead something significant
to say about his philosophy as such. And here lies, I think, one of the
important merits of Safranski’s book: namely, to have pointed to some of the
possible links connecting Nietzsche’s ideas to some of the circumstances of his
life, to have revealed the subtle and unexpected ways in which one of the
boldest and most provocative philosophies of the nineteenth century has been
nourished, “tested” and eventually given (brilliant) shape, by such a tormented
life as that Nietzsche lived before his mental collapse in January 1889.
Another interesting thing
about Safranski’s book is, I think, the fact that it seems to be narrating
Nietzsche’s “philosophical biography” somehow from within. As a result of what might be called a deep spiritual
empathy (Einfühlung),
Safranski succeeds in conveying the impression to the reader that his story of
Nietzsche’s intellectual development is such that only an unseen eye-witness to the whole process by which Nietzsche’s
philosophy was born, given shape and disseminated would have been able to tell.
Nietzsche’s “life was a
testing ground for his thinking. The essay was a mode of living.” (p. 28) This
is one of the central ideas around which Safranski’s book is clustered, and thanks
to which the intensity and vividness of his account on Nietzsche’s life is as
it were assured from the very beginning. Nietzsche had a special relationship
with the act of writing. To him writing was not a current activity among many
others, but played a privileged role throughout his life: “At first he simply
wrote about his own life; then he wrote with all of the life force he could
muster, and ultimately he wrote to stay alive.” (p. 25) For all his not very
friendly attitudes to religion, writing had for him, ironically, all the marks
of a liturgical gesture, which he
performed properly, with all the required solemnity, commitment and
self-dedication. The famous scene of inspiration he talks about in detail in Ecce Homo (chapter “Zarathustra”), to
give only one example, is highly
indicative of his quasi-religious approach to the act of writing. From this
point of view, he would have been in complete agreement with Kafka’s (otherwise
enigmatic) saying that writing is
praying.
As a matter of fact, the
importance he attributes to writing is only one facet of the complex
relationship he bears with the realm of language.
To him, language is not an external fact,
merely a “social tool” to pragmatically use in communication, but language
belongs to our ultimate ontological make up. Through language only we can shape
and order ourselves, and it is through language that we eventually discover, if
not simply “invent”, ourselves. And Nietzsche grasped this fact quite early in
his development, and valued it so highly that he eventually made it one of the
distinctive features of his approach to himself and to the world around:
“Self-configuration through language became a passion for Nietzsche. It
contoured the unique style of his philosophy, which blurred the boundaries
between detection and invention. Since he considered philosophy a linguistic
work of art and literature, thoughts were inextricably bound to their
linguistic form. The magic of his linguistic virtuosity would suffer
considerable loss if his words were to be expressed any other way.” (p. 55)
This feature, again, points to a certain sacerdotal
dimension of the act of writing: like within a sacred text, the words
written down in the moment of inspiration cannot be changed, they belong to –
and are the expression of – an “order of things” that cannot be otherwise than
it is.
At the same time, this
language-centered philosophy, by the emphasis it necessarily places on the play
of “beautiful” appearances, by the sophisticated system of rhetorical
procedures and techniques it brings about, reveals another major Nietzschean
contribution: his ontologically rooted aestheticism, the notion that the fundamental
question about existence – human existence included – is whether or not it is
justified from an aesthetical point of view. More precisely, as he puts it in The Birth of Tragedy (§
5): “Existence and the world are eternally justified solely as an aesthetic
phenomenon.” Raised in his first philosophical writing, this is a issue that
will in some way or other remain central to all his subsequent works, and serve
as a hallmark of his style of philosophizing. If something exists only insofar
it appears as being “beautiful” and “justified” aesthetically, then the truth
itself, along with its definition, criteria, and means of “production”, is to
be dramatically reconsidered: “Cognition is a power play of creative forces, a
process that culminates in successful, powerful, and vital forms and ideas.
Whatever holds its own in this way is called truth.” (p. 287) As it were, the
knowledge is a sophisticated playful process through which certain
configurations of factors, as they appear from certain perspectives, are given priority and truth value, just as others
are removed or neglected. As far as the production of the philosophical
discourse is concerned, a proposition becomes true when it is aesthetically
irreproachable. In Safranski’s words, “[t]he beauty and strength of
propositions become virtually synonymous with their truth value.” (p.180)
It should be noted at this
point that there is nothing superficial or facile about this metaphysical
aestheticism. On the contrary, as Nietzsche saw it, this was a very serious and
dangerous concept to work with, it was a matter of life and death as it were,
which conferred upon his philosophical exercise the dreadful aura of vivere periculosamente: “Unlike
Schopenhauer, Nietzsche was powerfully attracted to Dionysian nature; he sought
to step right up to the abyss because he envisioned even more alluring secrets
there and considered himself impervious to vertigo.” (p. 50) Seen in this
light, Nietzsche’s choice to become a philologist should be regarded not as,
say, an attempt at gaining a secure position within the establishment of the
German humanistic scholarship of the day, but as some form of sophisticated
disguise, as a mask by means of which
he sought to obtain what Unamuno would later call la seguridad de la consciencia: a minimal existential protection
against the devastating “black despair” that looking the abyss into face brings
necessarily about. As Safranski says, “[h]e had chosen philology as a means of
discipline in the face of temptation by the enormous horizons of perception and
artistic passions. The ‘groping hand of instinct’ had obviously not led him to
travel out onto the open sea, but instead recommended that he be content with
looking out onto the horizon from the shore.” (p. 43)
As such, his subsequent
failure as a professional philologist was not only unavoidable, but in some way
carefully “engineered”. He did nothing to prevent it; on the contrary, he did
almost everything to trigger it. For example, well aware as he was that The Birth of Tragedy would not be
exactly what his teachers, mentors, and colleagues were expecting from him, he
proceeded however to write it: “surmising that, while it would most likely not
move him ahead in his profession, it would afford him a better understanding of
himself. […] Still grounded in philology, but overpowered by the will to dance,
Nietzsche wrote his first masterpiece: The
Birth of Tragedy.” (p. 58) Yielding to the “will to dance” is indeed a
gesture whose boldness and loftiness are not, I am afraid, the most common
currency within the academic world. After the book was published, Ritschl, one
of his former mentors, one of those who supported him “unreservedly”, called it
“witty carousing” (p. 83). Nevertheless, the most symptomatic reaction came
from Ulrich Wilamowitz-Moellendorf, the all-famous classical philologist. As a
matter of fact, Wilamowitz-Moellendorf functioned in a way as the mouthpiece
for the entire philological establishment, as his views on The Birth of Tragedy expressed the concerns and fears of an entire
generation of scholars that was then confronted with a completely new approach
to the classical scholarship: “Let Mr. Nietzsche keep his words, let him take
up the thyrsus and move from India to Greece, but he should step down from the
podium from which he is supposed to be teaching scholarship; let him gather
tigers and panthers at his knees, but not Germany’s young generation of
philologists.” (p. 83)
In a letter to his doctor Otto Eiser, written in early
January 1880, Nietzsche makes this terrible confession: “My existence is an awful burden – I would have dispensed
with it long ago, were it not for the most illuminating tests and experiments I
have been conducting in matters of mind and morality even in my state of
suffering and almost absolute renunciation – the pleasure I take in my thirst
for knowledge brings me to heights from which I triumph over all torment and
despondency.” (p. 178) The major revelation that this passage brings forth is,
I think, the fact that Nietzsche had taken his own life as a testing ground for his philosophical
exercise, for all his bold ideas and dangerous speculations. Almost needless to
say, such a fact is very difficult to overestimate. It is one of the most
interesting enterprises ever undertaken, at least to such a scale, in the
history of Western philosophy, and it is probably this particular feature, more
than any others, that confers on Nietzsche’s philosophizing an unparalleled intensity,
seriousness and gravity. However strange, “exotic”, peculiar or revolting his
philosophy might appear to you, you cannot
simply ignore or overlook it, but you have to consider it seriously. Even if
one completely disagrees with Nietzsche’s answers, one cannot deny the pathos
and authenticity of the questions he sought to answer through his philosophy.
There is a profound sense of intellectual honesty and frankness in his
enterprise, not to say anything about its unsayable heroism.
It is the letter to
Nietzsche’s doctor quoted above, with its mentioning of the torments,
sufferings and all the rest, that betrays one of Nietzsche’s most obsessive
questions he had incessantly asked himself from the very beginning of his
philosophical efforts: “How much truth can a person endure without being
destroyed by it?” In more general and philosophical terms, this question is, as
Safranski puts it, “whether knowledge and the will to truth are really
subordinate to the ‘instinct to preserve the species’, or whether the will to
truth might break free from life and even take aim against it.” (p. 236) The
issue certainly belongs to the Schopenhauerean legacy, but the way in which it
was reformulated by Nietzsche, the pathos and intensity he invested in it, made
it almost unrecognizable. In the last instance, all what Nietzsche did
throughout his writings was to grapple with this overwhelming question: “Might
the will to truth aspire to become the master of life instead of its servant,
even if the result is the destruction of life?” And he eventually paid with his
own mind for having dared to do so.
Finally, let me also add
that, although Safranski deeply empathizes with Nietzsche’s case, seeing his
philosophical development “from within” and looking into its most intimate secrets
with passionate understanding and dedication, he does not however omit to
mention and lucidly discuss those odd parts in Nietzsche of which Alexander
Nehamas once said: they are “at best incomprehensible and at worst embarrassing
and better forgotten, or at least tactfully over-looked.” (Nietzsche: Life as Literature, Harvard University Press, 1985, p.
vii) Nietzsche wrote, for example: “In
order to have a broad, deep, and fertile soil for artistic development, the
overwhelming majority must be slavishly subjected to the necessities of life to
serve a minority beyond the measure of its individual needs.” (p. 148) Most
importantly, it should be immediately remarked that this was not simply an
attempt at empathetically understanding the Greek polis on Nietzsche’s side, some peculiarity belonging to his views
as a professional historian. No, this belonged to his opinions on the “current
affairs”, and was part of his vision of an “ideal society”: “He was against
shortening the length of the workday from twelve hours a day to eleven in
Basel. He was a proponent of child labor, noting with approval that Basel
permitted children over the age of twelve to work up to eleven hours a day.”
(p. 148) On reading such passages, one cannot help thinking that, in a way, it
has been better that it was Marx’s utopia that was sought to be put into
practice and not Nietzsche’s.
It is this extremely
revealing confession, by Lou Andreas-Salomé, Nietzsche’s muse for
a short while, that I would like to conclude my (undeservedly schematic) review
of Safranski’s book with: “Strange how in the course of our conversation we
managed inadvertently to descend into abysses and those dizzying places people
go along to gaze down into the depths. We have always chosen the mountain goat
paths. If somebody had listened in on our conversation, he would have thought
that two devils were talking.” (p. 254)
© 2002 Costica Bradatan
Costica Bradatan is a doctoral candidate in
philosophy at the University of Durham (UK). His research interests include
early modern philosophy, history of ideas, philosophy and literature,
philosophy of religion. Bradatan is the author of two recent books (in
Romanian): An Introduction to the History
of Romanian Philosophy in the XX-th Century (Bucharest, 2000) and Isaac Bernstein’s Diary (Bucharest,
2001), as well as of numerous book chapters, scholarly papers, articles and
reviews, published in both Romanian and English.
Categories: Philosophical, Memoirs