Philosophy and This Actual World

Full Title: Philosophy and This Actual World: An Introduction to Practical Philosophical Inquiry
Author / Editor: Martin Benjamin
Publisher: Rowman & Littlefield, 2002

 

Review © Metapsychology Vol. 7, No. 23
Reviewer: Ben Mulvey, Ph.D.

In his An Enquiry Concerning
Human Understanding
David Hume says, "The mere philosopher is a
character, which is commonly but little acceptable in the world, as being
supposed to contribute nothing either to the advantage or pleasure of society;
while he lives remote from communication with mankind, and is wrapped up in
principles and notions equally remote from their comprehension."  Martin Benjamin is equally annoyed with this
conception of philosophers and has dedicated his professional life to demonstrating
the relevance of philosophical thinking to real human problems.

I met Martin Benjamin twenty-five
years ago when I was assigned to be his teaching assistant in his biomedical
ethics course.  I found him to be a
masterful teacher because the explanations he presented to his inexperienced
students were clear and he made the relevance of philosophical thinking to real
problems of life and death and human interaction obvious.  These qualities are evident on every page of
his new book, Philosophy and This Actual World.  Consider this typical comment from
Benjamin’s Introduction, "A pragmatic temperament…acknowledges that genuine
philosophical questions are not a matter of intellect alone.  They are raised by the whole person and
involve both the street…and the classroom" (3).  The spirits of William James and Ludwig Wittgenstein figure
prominently in the book.

The book, characterized by clearly
written prose throughout and designed to speak to the "general
reader" (xii), is divided into eights chapters of approximately equal
length.  The first chapter deals
primarily with method and perspective and each subsequent chapter addresses an
important philosophical problem or related group of problems, such as the
nature of truth, the nature of reality, the problem of free will, whether
ethical thinking yields real answers, policies regarding physician-assisted
suicide in a democratic society, the definition of death, and the question of
life’s meaning.

Benjamin is justifiably
dissatisfied with how modern philosophy has dealt with a number of perennial
problems.  Interestingly, it is the way
that modern philosophy, taking its method form Descartes, conceives of these
problems that contributes to their apparent intractability.  That is, once one adopts the perspective of
the Cartesian subject, a disembodied spectator outside of space and time, one
is faced with irresolvable conflicts. 
Conceiving, instead, "the subject of inquiry as pragmatic (an
embodied social agent)…results in different philosophical questions about knowledge,
reality, mind, freedom, and ethics" and allows resolution of those
conflicts "for all practical purposes" (20).  It is in the ensuing chapters where this
insight is most directly applied to some of the classic problems of philosophy.

In Chapter Two, "Language,
Meaning, and Truth," Benjamin highlights the importance of getting clear
on the concepts of language, meaning, and truth because "we raise
philosophical questions in…words and then "try to determine which
of a possible variety of answers is true" (28).  A Cartesian subject implies that language is both self-taught and
private.  But in a very clear exposition
of some of Wittgenstein’s most famous insights, Benjamin shows how these
Cartesian implications are mistaken and misleading.  We know that "normal human beings do not develop their genetic
capacities for language apart from interactions with members of a linguistic
community" (34), and "[r]ecent work in cognitive science and early
child development shows that the playful, embodied interactions between parents
and children and the world result in a child’s readily solving a number of
traditional philosophical problems…" (36), such as whether there really is
a world outside of our minds, whether and how our words match up with that
reality, and whether there are any minds other than our own.

Similarly, in Chapter Three,
"Knowledge and Reality," Benjamin shows that much philosophical worry
can be dissipated once we abandon our unattainable search for absolute
certainty and redefine that notion in practical or pragmatic terms (61).  In Chapter Four, "Mind and Will,"
a chapter that may be of particular interest to those in the mental health
field, Benjamin addresses two classic philosophical issues, the nature of the
relationship between minds and brains and the issue of whether or not human
beings have free will.  Once again, by
applying the pragmatic insights outlined in the first chapter, Benjamin’s
analysis yields new, more useful, perspectives on these old problems.

Chapter Five, "Ethics,"
concerns the nature and justification of ethics.  Here Benjamin enters into the so-called nature versus nurture
debate and shows how perspectives on this debate have serious implications for
our understanding of the nature of morality. 
Once again, rejecting the idea of a Cartesian disembodied rational agent
in favor of an embodied social agent "leads to a new and more promising
understanding of the origins of ethics and the sources of moral motivation:
evolutionary biology" (104). 
Evolutionary biology in turn supports the notion of social, embodied subjects
and the idea that interpersonal moral sensitivities are simply part of the
human biological organism that evolve and impact our behavior in much the same
way as do our bodies.  This does not
rule out a role for ethical decision-making. 
But it may well alter our conception of it.  Again, the pragmatic point of view understands the concept of
certainty differently from absolute Cartesian certainty, emphasizing what
Benjamin calls "personal and interpersonal coherence" (122).  Can we make moral judgments with the
confidence we find with mathematical certainty?  Clearly not.  But all is
not lost.  As Benjamin explains it,
"[a]s each part of a ship is subject to repair and replacement, no aspect
of a moral framework is, in principle, immune to correction or
improvement.  On the open sea, however,
an imperfect ship is better than no ship at all."  (112)

In Chapter Six, "Democratic
Pluralism," Benjamin continues the discussion of the previous chapter and
confronts what might be called the Enlightenment myth, perhaps fueled by the
Cartesian perspective, that the consistent application of reason to human
affairs will ultimately result in harmony. 
On the contrary, claims Benjamin, "[s]o long as individuals…enjoy a
certain amount of freedom to think and act for themselves, there will be
conflicts between good and important moral values and principles that cannot be
resolved by reason.  This is a fact
about ethics—the fact of moral pluralism…. (124).  As in the previous chapter, the conclusion
here is not a reason to despair.  It is
an impetus to refine our understanding of what it is to live in a community,
adopting a "democratic temperament," and to align our methods and
expectations accordingly.  In this
chapter, Benjamin applies insights from some of his earlier work on
"integrity preserving compromise" and explores the contentious public
policy debate surrounding the issue of physician-assisted suicide, once again
demonstrating the "usefulness" of clear philosophical reflection.

In Chapter Seven, "Determining
Death," he takes a similar approach using the debates about the
appropriate definition of death as a fruitful illustration. And in Chapter
Eight, "Meaningful Lives," he shows that a one can construct a
meaningful life with or without the notion of a god or God.  This is not another pedantic or abstract
philosophical exercise.  Benjamin’s
conclusions here could not be more timely and they are worth remembering.  "Pragmatists will, insofar as possible,
respect and politically accommodate individuals holding fundamentalist and
other nonpragmatist beliefs, even if they think they are mistaken.  The only restriction is that such beliefs
must not be harmful to or forced upon those who do not willingly share
them" (183).

This book is an easy read, not
because it is entertaining in a simplistic way, but because it is
intellectually engaging on a level that most readers, regardless of the level
of their philosophical sophistication, can grasp.  The prose is clear and not cluttered with footnotes and attempts
to prove its academic merit.  Benjamin
includes a helpful bibliographic essay at the end of the book for those who may
want some guidance in finding sources or suggestions for further reading.  I would use the book in college-level
introductory philosophy courses, I would recommend it to me peers both inside
as well as outside academia.  Most
importantly, this book is an illustration of the lesson I learned in my own
relationship with Martin Benjamin, that when done well, "[p]hilosophical
inquiry and understanding can…make significant contributions to a
democratically pluralistic society and to the lives of its members" (178).

 

©
2003 Ben Mulvey

 

Ben Mulvey,
Ph.D., is an Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Division of
Humanities of the College of Arts and Sciences at Nova Southeastern
University.  He received his doctorate
in philosophy from Michigan State University specializing in political theory
and applied ethics.  He teaches ethics
at NSU and is a member of the board of advisors of the Florida Bioethics
Network. 

Categories: Philosophical, Ethics