The Psychology of Parental Control

Full Title: The Psychology of Parental Control: How Well-Meant Parenting Backfires
Author / Editor: Wendy S. Grolnick
Publisher: Lawrence Erlbaum, 2003

 

Review © Metapsychology Vol. 9, No. 13
Reviewer: John D. Mullen, Ph.D.

To my mind child rearing has three
important goals, the protection of the child’s right to experience a childhood,
the enjoyment by the parent of the wonders of this unique human relationship
and the protection of the child’s natural development into an autonomous
adult.  Each of these three requires
that the behaviors, attitudes and beliefs of the child be influenced in
deliberate ways by parental actions. 
Wendy Grolnick’s book, the Psychology of Parental Control,
provides a taxonomy of concepts within which to consider issues of parental
influence, a review of the psychological literature, and a point of view
concerning what is likely to work and what is not.  It is a clear, well-written and practical text that would be
useful for academic courses in psychology and teacher education and to parents
as well.

The first part of the book examines
and clarifies a set of concepts necessary to discuss the wide-ranging and
diverse research into parenting effectiveness. 
Perhaps the best known of the concept sets in this area is Baumrind’s
tripartite division of parenting styles into authoritarian, permissive and
authoritative (p. 5).  Grolnick borrows
freely from this tradition to be sure but places her emphases elsewhere.  In a nutshell Grolnick wants to argue that
attempting to control a child’s behaviors, attitudes and beliefs will not
produce as successful a set of results as the alternative approach, which she
terms "autonomy support". 
Baumrind’s typology does not, in Grolnick’s view, lend itself to making
this point as clearly as it should be made. 
But Grolnick’s main thesis puts a heavy burden upon the ordinary term
"control" and so requires a good deal of semantic housekeeping.  She addresses this task not by a series of
precise definitions but through a process of differentiating her concept of
control from other ideas with which it might become conflated.  Of course parents need to be "in
control" of their children, for example, to protect them from obvious
dangers, to assure civil behavior in others’ homes and to get them their shots
whether they like it or not.  In
Grolnick’s hands, then, "controlling behaviors" must become a
technical term, narrower and more precise than its ordinary use
counterpart. 

Grolnick begins with three basic
needs that every person has, the needs to feel autonomous, competent and related
to others.  Control oriented parenting
interferes with the fulfillment of these needs.  Parents are either controlling or autonomy supportive through the
environments that they create for their child. 
An environment is controlling to the degree that children do not,
"… feel that they initiate their actions …" (13) and do feel coerced,
as if they have no choice, as if their behavior is initiated from without.  In an autonomy supportive environment a
child can perceive himself or herself as the locus of causality (what some
philosophers call "agent causality").  Grolnick does not attribute such characteristics to objective
features of environments since different individuals may experience the same
environment as either controlling or autonomy supportive.  It is, "… the ‘functional significance’
of the environment that makes it controlling or autonomous." (15).  While this fact is likely to be true, if it
is taken to heart it will seriously complicate any attempts to give concrete
practical advice concerning what to do and avoid as parents.  Fortunately Grolnick ignores the point
except when discussing cultural differences.

Control should not be confused with
structure, the latter being a system of clear rules, for example, explicitly
stating times a child is expected to be home. 
The controlling parent will convey these rules with threats whereas the
autonomy supportive parent will convey them with an understanding of their
burden and an explanation of their necessity. 
This is similar of course to Baumrind’s authoritarian vs. authoritative
parent. 

Eschewing control should not be
confused with disengagement.  Grolnick
distinguishes involvement from the family therapy concept of
"enmeshment", the latter referring to high levels of closeness with
low levels of autonomy.  Involvement and
autonomy are not opposing characteristics of relationships and both need to be
optimized (25).  The philosophical
reader will think here of the Sartrean rejection of this idea and of his world
of "being for others" in which, "Hell is other people."

It would seem reasonable to say
that some control is good for a child and that how much is good will depend
upon the child’s personality and his or her developmental level.  Grolnick rejects this idea, asserting instead
that controlling behaviors are bad for children at all levels of control, for
all personalities and for all ages of children, though she is willing to agree
that such variations may be true of structure. 
This sweeping rejection of control could be supported by semantic stipulation,
that is by defining control as some form of error or excess, so that behaviors
that are of benefit to children, and seem like forms of control, literally
cannot be controlling.  If this is what
is happening, Grolnick’s main point against controlling behaviors by parents is
in danger of being tautological.  One
way that Grolnick wiggles out of this is by conceptualizing control as a
relationship style or context rather than as a specific technique or practice.  "… when control refers to pressuring,
intrusive behavior, and motivating children through bribes and other external
inducements, the control undermines children’s motivation …" (32).  On this view a good spanking, which is a
favorite bëte noir of bad parenting, may not be an example of control if
done within a certain type of parent-child relationship.  Although this dulls the bite of Grolnick’s
main point against control, it assures it of empirical content and brings it
closer to the truth.

The book provides an extensive
review of literature in favor of the idea that autonomy support is good and
controlling behaviors are bad for children. 
These results are presented clearly though largely without a critical
eye.  Some examples:  "Children with warm, contingent
relations in early life were more likely to comply with parental … directives
…" (31); "… structural behaviors are more facilitative when they are
combined with autonomy support. " (28); "… children who saw their
parents as controlling tended to be more negative about their parents’ involvement
[in school matters]. " (25); " … parents who were rated as more
autonomy supportive had children who reported more autonomous
self-regulation…" (57); "Parents who were more supportive and who
were less likely to interfere in their children’s communications …[in moral
discussions] … had children who were more advanced in their moral
reasoning" (65). 

I have problems with relying so
heavily upon results such as these, even if we tend from common sense alone to
agree with them.  The reason is that Grolnick
has largely ignored the critique of correlational studies such as these that
has been developed by behavioral geneticists. 
There are two prongs to that criticism. 
The first is that such studies ignore the possibility that the
correlations are explainable by genotypic relationships.  For example, why would children of more
supportive parents have more advanced moral reasoning?  One answer could surely be a correlation between
supportive parenting and the IQ of the parents coupled with a correlation
between advanced moral reasoning and the (inherited) IQ of the child.  The second issue involves the general
inability of behavioral genetics to detect significant parenting effects from
within the admittedly important range of environmental effects that shape
children.  Part of this critique has
been the pervasive diagnosis of child-to-parent effects that have previously
been read as parent-to-child effects. 
For example, perhaps the reason why children who see their parents as
controlling tend to be more negative about parental involvement is that the
children were temperamentally negative to begin with in ways that prompted
parents to be controlling.  Grolnick has
a brief treatment of child-to-parent effects but only in the context of
explaining what prompts parents to be controlling.  She does not use these results, or those detecting genetic
influence, to cast doubt upon the leaps from correlation to cause that have
been so prominent in the developmental literature.  (For a good review of the issue of parenting effects see Parenting
and the Child’s World: Influences on Academic, Intellectual, and
Social-Emotional Development
by John G. Borkowski, Sharon Landesman Ramey
and Marie Bristol-Powers, Lawrence Erlbaum, 2002.)  In addition, I would expect a work that offers advice on what
works and what does not work in parenting to give some consideration to Judith
Rich Harris’ group socialization theory, which provides a cogent critique of
the parenting literature and an alternative explanation for how children
develop the behaviors and other traits that they do (see Harris’ The Nurture
Assumption
. Free Press, 1998.)

That having been said, there is
much in this book to recommend.  The
critique of rewards-based behavior control, in parenting and even more important
in teaching, is very important.  As a
teacher of ethics and general philosophy to student teachers I have found that
behavior analysis is presented to students as a panacea for all the problems of
motivating class work and controlling the room, with never a mention of the
ways that it could inhibit learning. 
The discussion of cultural and ethnic differences in the perceptions of
parental behavior is an antidote to those who profess to own a surefire method.  The discussion of parental ego involvement, particularly
as it relates to the child’s intelligence and school success, could be enlarged
into a book unto itself and should then be distributed without cost to every
upwardly mobile parent who refuses to allow his or her child to have a
childhood.  The discussion of
informational vs. controlling praise as interesting as it is
counter-intuitive.  

In summary, I recommend this book
and hope that it gets a wide reading.

 

©
2005 John D. Mullen

 

John D. Mullen, Ph.D., Department
of Philosophy, Dowling College, New York.

Categories: Relationships