Anger

Full Title: Anger: The Seven Deadly Sins
Author / Editor: Robert A. F. Thurman
Publisher: Oxford University Press, 2004

 

Review © Metapsychology Vol. 9, No. 41
Reviewer: Tony Milligan, Ph.D.

This is the latest offering in a
handy series of short books on our favorite faults. Although he provides some
treatment of Seneca and Aristotle on anger (more so the former than the latter)
what Thurman offers is essentially a short Buddhist meditation on the topic. Buddhism
is very much his field. This is not to say that he advances the implausible
claim given on the dust cover (in the West anger is seen as unavoidable, in the
East it is seen as something we can overcome). What it does mean is that he is
much more in his stride once he gets beyond his gloss on Western accounts and
gets closer to the Buddhist material.

Having said that, one of the most
instructive features of the book is the way in which his outline of (one strand
of) Buddhist thought on anger reveals it to be substantially in agreement with
Seneca. (Someone whose reading of Seneca is a little closer than Thurman’s
might find interesting similarities here.)  Be that as it may, Thurman
structures his case against anger around a contrast between resigning to
anger
and resigning from anger where  the former involves the view
that you can do nothing about anger and the latter involves the view that anger
can (and should) be totally eradicated. Thurman’s middle way between
them turns out to involve a gradualist attempt to uproot anger rather than a
sudden leap out of it. This looks suspiciously like resigning from anger
but he may do just enough to convince the reader otherwise.

The contrast between the two
paths, although not slavishly adhered to, is given more prominence than any
account of exactly what anger itself is. (Another similarity to Seneca, but his
manuscript has the excuse of being somewhat incomplete.) Even in a work with a
limited remit this is something of a shortcoming. The closest he comes to
pinning down his subject is when he treats it as an impulse to a
harmful response
. This falls short of even a provisional definition given
that whatever impulses are, there might happen to be various different impulses
of precisely this sort. Nevertheless, Thurman does disclose enough about anger
to develop his Buddhist theme. As anger is an impulse to harm, Buddhism views
it as a bad thing.

Rather than harming the other,
Buddhism would have us cultivate compassion. This is no easy matter, but some
definite steps are outlined: tolerance of suffering, forbearance and forgiveness.
When we act in anger we act slavishly, not freely. The same is true of others
who harm us, so why should we be angry with them? The position at this point reads
more and more like Seneca: anger involves us in the cognitive error of thinking
that others harm us freely rather than under constrain. Nevertheless, Thurman’s
ongoing source is not Seneca but the Tibetan Buddhist Shantideva. (He happens
to be a rather prestigious translator of the latter.)

The customary metaphorical
devices are deployed to outline the Buddhist case: we have so much energy
deployed in this way or that. The trouble with anger is that it
is such a waste of energy. Ultimately we are to resign to anger but not
in the sense of accepting its energy as we find it, but in the sense of
reclaiming it for more useful purposes. My problem here is not with the
hydraulic/energy metaphor. If Plato and Freud can use it then so can Buddhists.
What troubles me is the way in which this theme of the uselessness of anger
tends to slip over into an instrumental preoccupation. Whether or not it helps
or hinders us on our personal/developmental/spiritual/moral journey there
remains the question of whether anger may not turn out to be a necessary part
of responding realistically to the particularity of extreme and dreadful
situations. 

If someone did not respond with
anger after entering the concentration camps would we not be inclined to
question whether they had really taken in what lay in front of their eyes? Equanimity
is all very well, but pursing it will be problematic if it is secured at the
expense of a realistic grasp of the situation. Seneca, Thurman, and Shantideva
would no doubt dispute the idea that there is any cognitive (or moral) failure.
If the harmful other is not a free agent then it is the angry man who is
getting it wrong.

Even so, does this not imply a
problematic diminution of our emotional repertoire? Right response surely cannot
mean responding in the same way time after time, otherwise we will not really be
responding to particular situations at all. What Thurman does seem to hint at,
and what may head off both problems is the possibility of a ‘Good hate’ which
is ‘a perfectly healthy attitude’. It would be nice to see the contrast between
this and anger developed a bit further but given that anger is taken by Thurman
to involve an impulse to harm, Thurman does leave enough clues to indicate that
something more systematic could be said. (i.e. ‘Good hate’ is not directed
towards persons; it involves self-control rather than the passing on of
suffering; it involves some recognition of the constraints upon their agency,
their lack of ‘real’ freedom.)

Where this leaves us is with a
nice little volume. It’s not vastly ambitious. It doesn’t overreach itself by
pretending to deal in more than a cursory way with anger within the Western
Canon. Instead, it focuses upon providing an interesting and worthwhile glimpse
over the fence.

           

 

© 2005 Tony Milligan

 

 

Tony Milligan completed his Ph.D.
on Iris Murdoch with the Philosophy Department at Glasgow University. The main
focus of his work is on moral philosophy, tragedy and the emotions. (He has a
partner called Suzanne who is much smarter than he is.)

Categories: Philosophical