Revolt, She Said
Full Title: Revolt, She Said
Author / Editor: Julia Kristeva
Publisher: Semiotext(e), 2002
Review © Metapsychology Vol. 7, No. 4
Reviewer: Adrian O. Johnston, Ph.D.
In a collection of interviews
entitled Revolt, She Said, Julia Kristeva performs quite an
extraordinary feat: she somehow manages to simultaneously trumpet the
importance of revolt as an essential feature of a properly human existence
while, nonetheless, ultimately endorsing a very un-revolutionary cultural and
political conservatism. This odd
position is best captured by a somewhat humorous aspect of this book: Kristeva
goes on and on, here and in other places, about how she’s a “foreigner,”
“stranger,” and “outsider” in relation to France (she came to Paris from
Bulgaria); and yet, one discovers that this book was supported by the French
Ministry of Foreign Affairs and the Cultural Service of the French Embassy in
the United States (it’s reminiscent of the fact that Noam Chomsky’s Syntactic
Structures was supported by the U.S. military). How does she manage to pull off this seemingly impossible
balancing act? As she tirelessly
reiterates in these interviews (as well as in her series of recent books
dealing with revolt), the original richness of meaning contained in the term “revolt”—Kristeva
herself, given her specific philosophical and psychoanalytic commitments,
treats revolt per se as a kind of psychical negativity—must be recovered by
refusing the contemporary tendency to reduce revolt to revolution qua
political rebellion—“to say that revolt is only politics is a betrayal of this
vast movement. People have reduced,
castrated and mutilated the concept of revolt by turning it only into politics”
(pg. 99).
However, Kristeva goes much further
than this. According to her, not only
must revolt and revolution be distinguished from one another—the latter should
be identified as a sinister, debilitating destruction of the former. Revolutions lead to the squelching of the
human capacity for revolt by simply encouraging conformity to a newly
established order; once the revolutionary moment passes, once the old regime
has been replaced, the time for questioning the status quo is relegated
to the past too (a consequence Kristeva bemoans). In The Sense and Non-Sense of Revolt, Kristeva maintains
that the traditional distinction between theory and practice, between thinking
and acting, merits serious reconsideration.
She hints that these two poles may indeed blur into each other. And yet, she categorically proclaims here
that, “to think is to revolt, to be in the movement of meaning and not the
movement of the streets…” (pg. 39). So,
apropos of revolt, there is, in actuality, a difference to be insisted upon
between theory and practice: revolt as creative intellectual, artistic, or psychological
thinking precludes revolution as political action. Once one starts operating as a revolutionary, once ceases
revolting.
In these interviews, Kristeva
displays a certain awareness of the obvious charge regarding the ideologically
insidious quality of her avowedly apolitical approach towards the notion of
revolt. She underscores the essentially
singular, personal quality of true revolt—it’s something to be discovered
through introspective self-reflection, in the privacy of the analyst’s consulting
room or in the working writer’s contemplative solitude. Revolts are effectuated through paintings,
sculptures, novels, poems, and so on.
Revolutions, by contrast, necessitate turning away from the intimate
sphere of the self due to the overriding emphasis on collective action. Furthermore, she flirts with the thesis that
all political revolutions terminate in totalitarian disasters (at this level,
she can be viewed as the polar opposite of Slavoj Žižek, who contends that the
specter of totalitarianism is a bogey man conjured up in order to sustain a
prohibition stigmatizing attempts to formulate genuine options to
liberal-democratic capitalism)—“When one is involved in politics it is very
difficult to escape dogmatism. The
entire history of political movements proves that they are permeable to
dogmatism. One wonders if the
realization of the revolt I am referring to is possible only in the private
sphere” (pg. 107). It’s difficult to
avoid concluding from all this that Kristeva’s basic, underlying suggestion is:
turn away from concrete socio-political engagements in favor of a focus upon
the self. Do the denizens of today’s
Western industrial societies (societies mired in what has been described as a
“culture of narcissism”) really need further encouragement to attend to
themselves?
At one point, Kristeva protests that
she hasn’t forgotten about real-world political issues. There are causes to which she’s still
devoted. Most of these have to do with
protecting the beloved “French way of life.” Understandably, some Europeans are justifiably worried that
globalization will lead to a situation where the European Union, in struggling
to rival the American economy, sacrifices positive aspects of its citizens’
lifestyles in favor of more “competitive” economic practices: workers will have to work longer for less
pay; employment benefits will be slashed and job security will be threatened; the
amount of annual vacation time will diminish;
the social welfare state will be eroded; cultural uniqueness will wither
under the homogenizing influence of “McWorld.”
These are valid concerns.
However, Kristeva seems most agitated about the loss of France’s
international cultural prestige and the Jospin-instated thirty-five hour
workweek. There is little to no talk
about material inequality between socio-economic classes. The political side to Kristeva’s “revolt,”
if it could be said to have one at all, appears limited to protecting the
intellectual, cultural, and lifestyle privileges of those already in a position
to partake of a certain sophisticated Gallic jouissance. What good is psychoanalysis to those who
cannot afford it? How upset are the
unemployed about the length of the workweek?
How can an illiterate immigrant living in France revolt, if revolt,
which Kristeva insists is vital to human well-being, is really only
accomplished by avant-garde literary movements? Equal access to employment, health care
(including mental health care such as analysis), and educational resources
(enabling an appreciation of the products of artistic revolts) are the most
pressing problems. Any ostensible
politics that has nothing to say about these matters is an empty “politics
without politics.” Kristeva ought to
just bite the bullet and openly admit that her theorizations about revolt are
thoroughly apolitical.
Another aspect of Kristevan revolt
is, as stated on the book’s back cover, “a permanent state of questioning… an
endless probing of appearances.” She
stipulates that, “Modern revolt doesn’t necessarily take the form of a clash of
prohibitions and transgressions that beckons the way to firm promises; modern
revolt is in the form of trials, hesitations, learning as you go, making
patient and lateral adjustments to an endlessly complex network…” (pg.
54). For someone acquainted with
psychoanalysis, this sounds like a description of obsessional neurosis (rather
than a liberating, creative power for renewal). In obsessional neurosis, individuals are paralyzed by interminable
questioning, finding themselves unable to act due to their sense of the
overwhelming complexity of circumstances.
They are stuck suffering in an endless deferral of action, ceaselessly
thinking with furious energy while waiting for who-knows-what to happen before
they feel comfortable enough to intervene in the course of their own
lives. What makes for the difference
between the neurotic’s use of “a permanent state of questioning” in the service
of procrastination and avoidance with regards to action and the revolt
celebrated by Kristeva in the exact same descriptive terms?
The quality of Kristeva’s scattered
remarks about various branches of psychoanalytic theory varies widely. Early on in the book, she aptly observes
that Deleuze and Guattari’s Anti-Oedipus “was breaking down an already open
door” (pg. 22). That is to say,
analytic clinicians were already grappling in great detail with psychotic and
pre-Oedipal states long before the fevered, post-May ’68 call for challenging
the family’s primacy in psychical life (one need only recall Melanie Klein’s
work in child analysis). And, as
Kristeva notes, Deleuze and Guattari attack psychoanalytic straw men,
especially when they oversimplify Freud’s portrayal of paternity. However, elsewhere, Kristeva indulges
herself in a similar manner when she categorically declares that, “a certain
type of psychoanalysis, namely American psychoanalysis, does not see this
interrogation as an open process, but as a standardization” (pg. 103). She evidently believes, as she explicitly
states, that analysts in the United States are determined to transform
homosexuals into heterosexuals and neurotics into corporate CEOs. This is ridiculous. Kristeva does nothing more here than parrot
Lacan’s now terribly outdated tirades from the 1950s against the ego psychology
of Hartmann, Kris, and Loewenstein.
It’s telling that Kristeva fails to name names in American
psychoanalytic circles as being guilty in light of her sweeping condemnation of
clinical practice on the other side of the Atlantic.
What those who have read Kristeva’s
previous books on the topic of revolt (The Sense and Non-Sense of Revolt
as well as Intimate Revolt) will find most discouraging and
disappointing about Revolt, She Said is that it confirms the worst
suspicions aroused by these prior works.
A disempowering subliminal message playing softly in the background of
the two volumes on “The Powers and Limits of Psychoanalysis” becomes a
deafening refrain in these interviews.
This little volume certainly does bring to mind other senses of the word
“revolt.”
© 2003 Adrian Johnston
Adrian Johnston, Ph.D. holds a position
as interdisciplinary research fellow in psychoanalysis at
Categories: Psychoanalysis, Philosophical