Understanding Marriage

Full Title: Understanding Marriage: Making It Work, or Knowing When to Leave
Author / Editor: Richard Taylor
Publisher: Prometheus Books, 2004

Buy on Amazon

 

Review © Metapsychology Vol. 8, No. 46
Reviewer: Nick Trakakis

This was the last book written by
the eminent philosopher and beekeeper, Richard Taylor, who died in October 2003
at the age of 83 after a nearly year-long battle with lung cancer.  Taylor was
keenly interested in such topics as friendship, love, sex, and marriage (see,
in particular, his 1982 book, Having Love Affairs), but here he reserves
his still-sharp philosophical mind for the institution of marriage, relying in
part on the knowledge gained as a certified marriage counsellor and, no doubt,
on his own experience of having been thrice married.    

 Taylor begins in Chapter 1
("Marriage and the Illusion of Happiness") by debunking the customary
conception of marriage, according to which a man and a woman fall in love,
become engaged soon after, and at an agreed-upon-date quite suddenly make the
transition to married status when, in the course of an elaborate and expensive ceremony,
the presiding cleric declares, "I now pronounce you man and wife".  Taylor
holds that "all this is a myth, an elaborate fabric of errors, nourished
by romantic notions that have little to do with life" (p.13).  A couple,
Taylor argues, can become married without any wedding or vows or ceremony of
any sort, as happens in ‘common law marriage’, where a couple may be deemed
married in virtue of cohabiting for a certain time.  But Taylor also adds that
"the mere legality of a marriage is not sufficient for the creation of a
genuine marital state" (p.16), and offers as examples a couple that
marries in order that one of the partners gains citizenship, and a man or woman
that marries only to acquire the wealth of the other person.  I would prefer to
call such couples ‘legally married’, and reserve what Taylor calls ‘true
marriage’ for couples that share a loving relationship.  Taylor, however,
counterintuitively claims that marriages that are merely legal "are not
marriages at all" (p.60).

  In any case, Taylor aims to
replace the legalistic and conventional conception of marriage with a more
philosophical one.  But as he is fully aware, any account of marriage must face
the fact that deep happiness often eludes married couples.  Taylor often points
out that any given marriage (in the United States) now has a fifty-fifty chance
of ending in divorce (unfortunately, this figure is not compared with divorce
statistics from other countries), and even when a married couple have no intent
to divorce their marriage may already be dead (as is illustrated by Taylor with
some harrowing real-life cases).  This raises a most interesting question:
"If the institution of marriage is in such a sorry state, why get
married?" (p.39).  To borrow an example of Taylor’s, would you sign up for
an exciting cruise if you were warned that there was a good chance you would
end up in some dismal foreign port from which escape was possible only at great
expense?  Taylor therefore examines whether there is any longer much point in
getting married, and he does this by comparing the benefits of marriage with
those of cohabitation.  Conventional marriage, Taylor concludes, has no
advantages over cohabitation other than providing, in some instances at least,
greater economic security.  But this does not address the original question,
for assuming that cohabiting couples separate just as often as conventionally
married ones, and at just as great an emotional and financial cost, the
question remains: Why bother?  (For an interesting attempt to develop such
considerations into a critique of marriage, see Dan Moller, "An Argument
against Marriage," Philosophy 78 (2003): 79-91; but see also Iddo
Landau’s perceptive response, "An Argument for Marriage," Philosophy
79 (2004): 475-81.)   

In Chapter 2 ("Ceremonies,
Vows, and the Meaning of Marriage"), Taylor insightfully identifies
courtship as one of the major reasons why many marriages fail.  Courtship, as
practiced today, involves a great deal of acting or role-playing, to the extent
that neither party comes to really know the other, especially the other’s
faults.  As part of "an intelligent alternative to this madness", Taylor
encourages governments to regulate that couples intending to get married must
live together for a certain minimum time before a marriage license can be
granted (p.49).  There is, however, little prospect of such a policy ever
becoming law, as Taylor acknowledges.

Taylor next casts his critical eye
on "the classic American wedding", with its arduous preparations,
culminating in a grand and costly ceremony, reception, and honeymoon €“ as Taylor
notes, "it would be difficult to imagine a less suitable way of entering
into marriage" (p.52).  Taylor then briefly discusses second marriages,
providing some clues as to why such marriages tend to be even more unstable
than the first ones (pp.54-56), before moving on to the topic of prenuptial
agreements, arguing that such agreements should be (but are unlikely to ever
be) a legal precondition for issuing a marriage license (pp.56-59).  In the
remainder of the chapter Taylor focuses on more central concerns, beginning
with ‘the meaning of marriage’ (pp.59-64).  Advocating an ethical rather than
legal conception of marriage, Taylor writes that "what is essential to
being married€¦is not anything readily seen, but rather a strong bond of love
between its partners that is lasting and gives meaning to the idea of lifelong
commitment" (p.60).  This bond of love, Taylor goes on to explain, is
founded on the promotion of the other’s sense of self-worth and the mutual
fulfillment of needs (pp.64-75).

In the next and relatively short
chapter (Chapter 3: "Failed Marriages"), Taylor notes that marriages
break down for a variety of reasons, some of which involve a real (and not
merely perceived) fault, such as physical abuse, while others involve some
surprise occurrence.  In this latter category Taylor includes the discovery of
infidelity, but also the sudden rise in one partner’s career prospects.  The
common denominator, however, in failed marriages is that "the partners
simply were not meeting each other’s needs" (p.89).    

The final chapter, "Dissolving
the Marriage", is procedural and quite practical in nature, detailing five
ways a marriage can be dissolved, beginning with the most acrimonious and moving
on to more friendly methods.  Taylor’s ‘Five Ways’ are, in short: (1) warfare:
litigation involving attorneys, with children likely to be used as weapons; (2)
arbitration: engaging a neutral, third party (such as a judge) to settle
disputes; (3) standard mediation: an agreement is reached in accordance
with divorce law but with the help of a mediator; (4) ‘open’ mediation:
as with (3), but the agreement is based not so much on the legal entitlements
as on the needs of the two parties; and (5) self-managed divorce: with
much co-operation, if not magnanimity, the two parties draw up an agreement
without turning to lawyers or mediators.  (I might point out that many of the
legalities discussed in this chapter will only be relevant to U.S. readers.)

The only criticism I could make of
this book is that it does not exactly live up to its sub-title, ‘Knowing When
to Leave’.  There is much discussion of knowing how to leave, but little
is said about the difficulties of, for example, determining whether it is better
to end a twenty-year marriage that has run into seemingly intractable
difficulties rather than trying to resurrect it.  This is, however, an
excellent book, combining philosophical and psychological insights with many
helpful practical suggestions on an important subject (one that is sadly
neglected by philosophers).  It would make an ideal gift for any engaged or
newly-wed couple.   

 

© 2004 Nick Trakakis

 

Nick Trakakis,
Department of Philosophy, Monash
University, Australia.

Categories: Relationships, Philosophical