Understanding Phenomenal Consciousness

Full Title: Understanding Phenomenal Consciousness
Author / Editor: William S. Robinson
Publisher: Cambridge University Press, 2004

Buy on Amazon

 

Review © Metapsychology Vol. 8, No. 49
Reviewer: Brad Weslake

The Epiphenomenalists
Return.

In recent philosophy of
mind, epiphenomenalism–that strain of dualism according to which the mind is
caused by the body but does not cause the body in turn—has undergone
something of a renaissance.  Contemporary epiphenomenalists bear only partial
resemblance to their more extravagantly metaphysical ancestors, however. 
Traditional epiphenomenalists thought that (at least) two sorts of mental
properties were epiphenomenal–intentional properties such as the meaning or
representational content of the propositional attitudes (beliefs, desires and
so on); and conscious properties such as awareness and the qualitative nature
of experience.  Contemporary epiphenomenalists, on the other hand, are largely
sanguine about the prospects for intentionality to be brought within the
purview of a physicalist worldview; what forces their dualism is one particular
feature of consciousness–what irks them are qualia, the
"what it is like" of experience (Nagel, 1974), or in the idiom
adopted by Robinson for the title of his book, what philosophers refer to as phenomenal
consciousness.

William Robinson’s Understanding
Phenomenal Consciousness
is a tightly argued and original defence of a form
of epiphenomenalism about consciousness he terms Qualitative Event Realism
(hereafter QER).  The most famous contemporary arguments for
epiphenomenalism, the knowledge argument due to Frank Jackson (see Ludlow et
al
, 2004) and the conceivability argument due to David Chalmers (1996),
have spawned a voluminous secondary literature, and it is a virtue of
Robinson’s book that he leaves these to one side, in order to form his own line
of attack.  Robinson is, like other epiphenomenalists, concerned primarily with
qualia; but perhaps uniquely among them, he thinks that the route to
epiphenomenalism lies not via knockdown a priori arguments concerning
what can in principle be integrated within a physicalist worldview, but rather
via careful evaluation of physicalist theories of consciousness, in light of
the current state of neuroscience.  Part I of the book forms the philosophical
core, where Robinson criticises rival views and motivates his own; while Part
II consists of a slightly more speculative sketch of how a science of
consciousness, coupled with the metaphysical stance of epiphenomenalism, might
proceed (that such a science is possible might seem a surprising claim, but
Robinson’s version of epiphenomenalism is, he argues, empirically
indistinguishable from a sufficiently fine-grained functionalism–the
metaphysical difference being whether the mind-body relation is one of
causation, or identity).

The book overall is
aimed primarily at a philosophical audience; it is densely populated with
argument, and is at times reasonably technical.  I expect it would be
challenging for those unfamiliar with the landscape of recent philosophy of
mind, though Robinson writes with such clarity and precision that it could
serve as a useful (though idiosyncratic; see below) introduction to some of the
territory in the philosophy of consciousness, for those already in the
neighbourhood.  In particular, I found his arguments for a range of theses concerning
the subjective properties of phenomenal experience to be exceptionally lucid
(notwithstanding their alleged literal spatiality).  These theses are for the
most part independent of the argument for epiphenomenalism.  Also especially
good are his criticisms of representationalist and higher order thought (HOT)
theories of consciousness in Chapters 4 through 7–readers who are
ontologically impressed by qualia in the first place and yet subscribe to one
or another of these physicalist theories will find their allegiance strongly
questioned.  But while Robinson is largely convincing on the negative side of
his metaphysical project, he is much less so on the positive side.  In the
remainder of this review I will restrict myself to two themes–firstly the architecture
of the book, and secondly a brief criticism of Robinson’s solution to the
causal problem for dualists.

 

Explaining Qualia.

As I have said, Robinson
(profitably, I think) eschews engaging with some of the most popular arguments
in the recent literature on consciousness.  However the framework in which he
sets the discussion is somewhat idiosyncratic.  Right from the beginning of the
book, the axis around which the argument turns is the debate between
"experiential realists" (those who believe in qualia) and
"minimalists" (those who do not).  But as Robinson himself (p. 10)
recognises, very few philosophers are minimalists (or at least, very few who
work on these problems).  The primary debates here are over the metaphysical status
of qualitative events, not their existence.  Setting up the debate in
this way has the happy result that his QER, though a form of epiphenomenalism,
turns out to be just one variant of experiential realism–which, in turn, makes
it seem as if motivating it is a matter of merely working out some details; of
merely resolving some in-house disputes with others in his camp–when in fact,
most physicalists and (presumably) all dualists are camped right there with
him.  Which is to say that setting up the debate in these terms serves to
rhetorically deflate what are generally taken to be the most important debates
in the area.

I take it this is
intentional.  Firstly, it is the sheerly phenomenal character of qualia
(independent of their status) that form the core of his criticisms of his
physicalist rivals.  Secondly, Robinson does not buy into the various
metaphysical debates over physicalism and dualism.  Neither physicalism nor
dualism are defined, and supervenience–the metaphysical relation around which
much mind-body debate has revolved in the last forty or so years–is left off
the conceptual map altogether in the early chapters, only making it onto the
stage by Chapter 8, or more than halfway through the book.  It is only at this
point in the book, too, that we get an explanation of why this is so.  Robinson
argues that just as posing a theoretical identity in absence of an explanatory
relation is empty, so is posing supervenience in absence of an explanation of
the necessity involved.  This is a common line of argument, and vindicates
somewhat the way the debate is set up.  But of course the epiphenomenalist has
no good explanation, of the sort demanded, either–and therefore placing the
emphasis on explanation would seem to count against any current theory
of consciousness.  What the debate becomes, once this is clear, is a matter of
what we ought to say were we to have some form of explanation (something of the
sort Robinson outlines in Part II, say)–and on these terms it is, at the
least, not clear that epiphenomenalism is left with any advantage.  Indeed, I
think it is left at a disadvantage, for reasons which follow.

 

Knowing Your Own Mind

In Chapter 10, Robinson
arrives at the hard question for the epiphenomenalism of his QER: How could it
be that we have knowledge of our phenomenal qualities if they are
inefficacious? The core objection here can be simply stated as follows:

Consider two worlds, one
where epiphenomenalism is true; and another where there are no qualia at all,
but that is otherwise a physical duplicate of the first.  How could a person in
either world know which world they are in?

The answer Robinson gives to this question is all-too-brief,
and in any case unsatisfying (in addition, coming late as it does, it turns out
to be narratively disappointing, given the strength of the earlier sections of
the book).  He notes that if epiphenomenalism is true, our believing and
speaking about phenomenal events counterfactually depends on the phenomenal
events themselves, since the neural causes of our relevant beliefs and language
are also the causes of the phenomenal events.  For example, we wouldn’t ever
(truly) report "I see a purple haze" unless we did see a purple
haze,  since one and the same neural event is the cause of both the purple haze
and our report.  And that is the whole account–remarkably, Robinson claims
that this is all that is needed to ground our knowledge of phenomenal
properties.  But of course, counterfactual dependence of this sort is radically
insufficient for knowledge.  On this model, for example, we should be able to
do our neuroscience from the armchair–since our beliefs and language
presumably have precisely the same counterfactual dependence relation with
their neural causes as they do with the phenomenal properties themselves
(indeed, Robinson’s account of knowledge would be perfect for the identity
theorist, for whom purple hazes just are neural events).

As Robinson (p. 169)
recognises, it might also be argued that his argument here is question begging,
in virtue of the conditional ("if epiphenomenalism is true…")
as highlighted above–surely you cannot argue for epiphenomenalism with a
premise conditionalising on its truth?  The reply Robinson gives to this
objection itself turns on the account of knowledge just criticised. What Robinson
says, in effect, is that we are entitled to believe in epiphenomenalism as an
argument to the best explanation, as follows:

1.      We have
knowledge of phenomenal events.

2.      Epiphenomenalism
is the best account of (our knowledge of) phenomenal events; therefore

3.      Epiphenomenalism
is true.

But again, the account of our knowledge of epiphenomenal
events given by Robinson is not up to the task. The problem, then, is simply
that epiphenomenalism does not in fact provide the best account of phenomenal
consciousness, since it leaves it mysterious how we could ever have knowledge,
form memories, and otherwise cognitively access phenomenal properties.  Midway
through the chapter, Robinson includes a meditation worthy of Descartes, where
he grapples with himself on this point–with a view to convince himself (and
us) that he is justified in believing in phenomenal events by the lights of his
view, and therefore that his account is defensible.  And he is in a real bind. 
On the one hand, the book is a sustained defence of epiphenomenalism; on the
other, he plainly knows he is undergoing phenomenal experiences.  But how?  The
conclusion seems to be that from these facts alone, there is no contradiction
in supposing epiphenomenalism compatible with our possessing knowledge of
phenomenal events.  But whatever other attractions epiphenomenalism may
have, they can’t help this part of the story–the gap needs filling.

Earlier in the book, as
I have said, much is made of the fact that physicalist accounts of phenomenal
consciousness seem unable to explain qualia; once Robinson has given his
own account, the natural question is whether he has improved the situation. 
Does establishing a causal connection between certain neural events and certain
qualitative events really explain qualia?  Does preserving their
separate metaphysical status somehow provide a stronger explanation than
reducing them to the very same neural events?  It is hard to see that this is a
difference in explanatory power, rather than a matter of whether one’s
metaphysics is seen to reflect the perceived specialness of the target domain. 
Indeed, once we see that explanatory force is equally a problem for the epiphenomenalist,
we might think the physicalist is actually better off–after all, she has a
story about how the legendary explanatory gap could be expressive not of an
ontological quandary, but simply of the fact that we don’t yet have any
explanations.

 

 

References

Chalmers, David J. 1996.
The Conscious Mind: In Search Of A Fundamental
Theory, Oxford University
Press, New York, 1996.

Nagel, Thomas. 1974.
"What Is It Like to Be a Bat?", in The Philosophical Review,
Vol. 83, No. 4, October 1974, pp. 435€“450.

Ludlow, Peter; Nagasawa,
Yujin; and Stoljar, Daniel (Eds). 2004. There’s Something About Mary: Essays
on Phenomenal Consciousness and Frank Jackson’s Knowledge Argument
, MIT
Press, Cambridge MA, 2004.

 

 

©
2004 Brad Weslake

 

Brad Weslake is a PhD candidate
at the Centre for Time, Department of Philosophy, University of Sydney,
Australia.  His dissertation concerns the temporal asymmetry of causation; he
is also interested in philosophy of mind and cognitive science.

Categories: Philosophical