Understanding Terrorism
Full Title: Understanding Terrorism: Psychosocial Roots, Consequences, and Interventions
Author / Editor: Fathali M. Moghaddam and Anthony J. Marsella
Publisher: American Psychological Association, 2004
Review © Metapsychology Vol. 8, No. 19
Reviewer: Roderick Nicholls, Ph.D.
The events of 9/11 have already
generated a huge number of publications, but readers looking to go beyond
exploitative instant journalism, political exposés or first person
human-interest accounts are often frustrated. For serious scholarly analysis
usually requires a long gestation period. However, this volume of essays
written by members of the American Psychology Association (APA) — and
dedicated to the victims of 9/11 — provides a valuable context for academics,
students and laypersons to engage in a discussion of international terrorism shaped
by the ongoing research of psychologists. The topic, of course, has been
extensively studied well before 9/11. Indeed, the long and very helpful list of
references included in Understanding Terrorism (283-314) suggests the
history and broad scope of existing research. Nevertheless, this timely
approach responds to an intellectual need that deserves to be satisfied. It
succeeds partly because the contributors respect cross-cultural perspectives
and recognize that if psychologists are to understand terrorism they require
substantial help from researchers in other fields. The editors, moreover, are
consciously motivated by an admirable sense of social responsibility. For the
goal of the collection as a whole, according to Moghaddam and Marsella is to
promote not just "peace" but a world-view "that can accommodate
and tolerate diversity, uncertainty and trust" (4).
Understanding Terrorism is
divided into three sections: the first concentrates on the conceptual
difficulties involved in the definition of terrorism, the second
delineates the psychosocial conditions that help us understand the formation
of terrorists or terrorist groups, and the third explores how psychologists can
best respond to the consequences of terrorism. This division generally
works well although definitional issues predictably over-run the boundaries of
section one. Several essays explicitly recognize questions standing in the way
of a consensus regarding the meaning of terrorism — for example, are the terms
"state terrorism" or "war on terrorism" incoherent? Yet
most stipulate a definition and proceed to develop a particular thesis. "Psychology’s
Response to Terrorism," the book’s concluding essay by Levant, Barbanel
and DeLeon, seems best able to avoid such questions because it is largely a
descriptive account of how the APA mobilized its members to respond to the
attack on New York, an event that surely meets all the relevant criteria of
terrorism. More specifically, although the authors mention efforts made to study
the consequences of the attack (conferences and research publications, etc.)
the heart of the essay is a first-hand story of an APA member trying to assist
those who needed help on the ground. In concert with the American Red Cross,
that is, Laura Barbanel helped relatives of victims and other emergency workers
such as firemen by acting as listener for those who wanted to talk, or
sympathetic companion for shocked and vulnerable people trying to cope with
limited information and physical resources.
Ironically enough, however, this
least conceptual essay in Understanding Terrorism ends up raising a most
intriguing question regarding psychology’s self-understanding. After
all, Barbanel notes that providing "emotional first-aid as it came to be
named" (269) is not the work for which professional psychologists are
trained, and she sharpens the edge on this point by saying that such
intervention "was not therapy" but "it was certainly therapeutic"
(271). This apt statement implies that "therapy," in the strict sense
of the word, might be appropriately offered only to a very small subset of the
large numbers of people who benefited greatly from the "therapeutic"
assistance of the diverse group of volunteer works during the immediate
after-effects of the terrorist attack. If so, then psychologists do not, on the
face of it, have a special professional responsibility to intervene
directly since they have no "therapeutic" expertise, in the
colloquial sense of the word. Another essay in section three, "The
Psychosocial Aftermath of Terrorism" by Danieli, Engdahl and Schlenger
also deals with the traumatic experiences of witnesses, relatives and emergency
workers in New York. However, when these authors claim that psychologists must "match
appropriate therapeutic interventions to particular forms of reaction"
(227) to trauma on the basis of an individual’s distinctive history,
personality and circumstances, "therapeutic intervention" clearly
means the sort of therapy that only psychologists are qualified to offer. The
essay explicitly discusses promising psychotherapeutic and pharmacological
treatments.
This sharp contrast is entailed
by methodology. For the primary concern of Danieli et al is to study the
empirical literature on the consequences of the New York attack, and this
literature is shaped by the conceptualization of trauma as a biomedical
phenomenon. Consider that post traumatic stress disorder (PTSD) is defined in
both the International Classification of Diseases (ICD-10) and the Diagnostic
and Statistical Manual of Mental Diseases (DSM-IV) in terms of a cluster of
symptoms that provide a focus for epidemiological researchers gathering data on
New Yorkers. According to the conclusion of one representative study,
approximately 75,000 New York public schoolchildren in grades 4-12 could be
said to be suffering from PTSD after 9/11 (237). Given the scientific data,
therefore, massive numbers of people would have benefited only from specialized
treatment after 9/11. Is this plausible? In "Terrorism and the Mental
Health and Well-Being of Refugees and Displaced Persons," Michael G. Wessells
sidesteps the possibility of methodological circularity. He acknowledges high
rates of PTSD amongst non-Western victims of violence and never suggests that
this category of Western psychiatry and psychology simply manufactures a
problem. Still, as someone with extensive experience assisting refugees and
displaced persons, Wessells warns against a "narrow focus on mental
illness" (248) and utilizes a holistic concept of well-being in his own
work. Hence trauma might best be understood in the context of spiritual beliefs
and social fragmentation. And effective intervention might depend upon an "ecological
approach" that does not privilege treatment but rather job training,
language acquisition, social networking, and the like.
Wessells aims to empower victims
of political violence. However, he concludes that the practical measures
required to achieve this goal also constitute the only way for psychologists to
help prevent the formation of terrorists. For it is futile to seek a
pathological "terrorist personality" type (259). Mental illness is no
more the root cause of terrorism than it is the prime consequence.
This essay, then, reflects back nicely upon the second section of Understanding
Terrorism. "Terrorism From A Peace Psychology Perspective" by
Wagner and Long, for example, points to life conditions — "hunger,
sickness and shelter for oneself or one’s family" (211) — as one
structural cause of terrorism; lack of security, self-determination and social
respect are additional causes that must be alleviated by civic education and
strategies for reconciling groups with a history of ethnic or religious
conflict. Since terrorism is not a necessary consequence of harsh
socio-economic conditions, most contributors probe special cultural
conditions. In "Understanding and Responding to Group Violence: Genocide,
Mass Killing and Terrorism" Ervin Staub discerns values and beliefs —
strong respect for authority, unhealed wounds of past victimization, etc. —
that magnify a dangerous sense of impotence. And "Terrorism and the Quest
for Identity" by Taylor and Louis contains an excellent discussion of how
a matrix of social, ideological and religious norms rooted in the lack of a "clearly
defined collective self" favor the emergence of terrorist groups (along
with their distinctive organizational ethos). Fathali M. Moghaddam’s "Cultural
Preconditions For Potential Terrorist Groups: Terrorism and Societal Change"
gives a comprehensive overview of terrorism’s "enabling conditions"
and highlights a theoretical assumption underlying other essays: the diverse "preconditions"
of terrorism do not operate consistent with a hierarchical psychological model,
but rather "reinforce one another and work as a Gestalt" (117).
As section two delves into
specifically cultural beliefs, another question about psychology’s
self-understanding appears. It can be glimpsed in the very title of an essay on
the purposeful rationality of terrorists: "Malevolent Minds: The
Teleology of Terrorism" by U.S. Defense Department psychologist Thomas Ditzler
(emphasis added). However, the best context in which to consider this question
is perhaps Albert Bandura’s insightful account, in "The Role of Selective
Moral Disengagement in Terrorism and Counterterrorism," of how terrorists
justify to themselves acts that horrify many people In one crucial passage, Bandura
sharply contrasts the "bad things" performed by terrorists and "good
things" (138) performed by a helicopter pilot during the My Lai massacre and
Nelson Mandela during the fight against apartheid. This moral judgment is
plausible. Nevertheless, in making it Bandura steps into the territory of
normative ethics. At one point he suggests that he is only acknowledging "experimental
research" (138) but in making such judgments he is actually embracing an
exceedingly metaphysical claim. For Bandura repeatedly insists that decent
people have the capacity to discern a "common humanity" underlying
any of our differences, whereas terrorists suffer from moral blindness. Rom Harré’s
"The Social Construction of Terrorism," by contrast, argues that
social psychology has no business answering substantive questions of good or
evil. He himself uses "that branch of discursive psychology called
positioning theory" (91) to delineate the complex manner in which George
W. Bush and Osama Bin Laden construct their moral identities out of mutually
interacting and "competing story lines" (92). Unlike a politician,
citizen or philosopher, however, he conceives his job as a psychologist to be
that of understanding the process not defending particular
protagonists.
Harré’s Bush and Bin Laden
example draws attention to the fact that many persons identified by mainstream
Western media as terrorists justify their actions in the name of Islam. Anthony
J. Marsella’s "Reflections on International Terrorism: Issues, Concepts,
and Directions" and, in more detail, Naji Abi-Hashem’s "Peace and War
in the Middle East: A Psychopolitical and Sociocultural Perspective"
respond by trying to do justice to the spiritual, ethical, and social values of
Islam. To a great degree, contributors such as Marsella and Abi-Hashem are
successful in deepening our understanding. Consider, though, that non-Muslims
are urged to recognize that jihad "has a personal as well as
communal dimension" (80) that resists appropriation as a rallying cry for
war against America by "demagogues who pander to simplistic solutions for
complex problems" (32). In passages such as these, Understanding
Terrorism is not just pointing to the diversity of Islam but defending
a specific version of it (in the face of an "extremist" or "fundamentalist"
theological interpretation). It needs to do so, moreover, precisely because
promoting peace is the book’s goal. At the same time, however, by implying that
"terrorists" are to be criticized partly because they distort
Islam, these passages reflect a tendency to repress this normative dimension.
This could be a matter of recognizing Harré’s disciplinary proscription against
embracing substantive moral or religious ideals. Or it might be due to the fact
that standard psychological categories and methods of classification are simply
not designed to grapple effectively with evaluative issues.
Nevertheless, the essays in
section one never adequately resolve the root conceptual ambiguity, namely,
that the word terrorist is used both to identify and morally condemn a
person. Perhaps the most satisfying attempt to do so is Brian Hallett’s "Dishonest
Crimes, Dishonest Language: An Argument About Terrorism." Hallett launches
a withering attack on conventional wisdom, according to which terrorism is "the
‘weapon of the weak’ needed to wage an asymetric war’ against" the
powerful (52). For he claims that a terrorist act can be distinguished from a
common crime by only two characteristics: the "theatrical aspect"
(50) of the crime and the "delusional self-interest … masquerading as
self-sacrifice" by which the terrorist justifies it (51). Hallett supports
these claims with a brilliantly conceived and well-executed argument that
contrasts a terrorist unfavorably with Ghandi’s satyargahi. He does this
from the point of view of political strategy as well as substantive values. He
argues, for example, that Ghandi, is more practical than Machiavelli and his discussion
of the relationship between terrorism and guerrilla warfare would be valuable
as a Defense Department backgrounder. It should be read in conjunction with Ditzler’s
"Malevolent Minds." Hallett’s essay accepts the necessity of making
value judgments but adjusts the character of his argument appropriately. Harré
might say that it is, therefore, a work of moral or political philosophy not
psychology. Nevertheless, it is a fine addition to an excellent collection.
© 2004 Roderick Nicholls
Roderick Nicholls is
an Associate Professor of Philosophy at the University College of Cape Breton
and has published in the areas of science, technology and society, applied
aesthetics and 19th century philosophy.
Categories: Ethics, Psychology