What Is Thought?

Full Title: What Is Thought?
Author / Editor: Eric B. Baum
Publisher: MIT Press, 2004

Buy on Amazon

 

Review © Metapsychology Vol. 8, No. 27
Reviewer: Aarre Laakso, Ph.D.

Baum is a well-known computer scientist, highly
and deservedly respected for his early work on neural networks and, more
recently, genetic algorithms and evolutionary programming–intriguing but
rather narrow technical topics in computer science. What is Thought? is
a broad-reaching book that concerns how meaning, understanding and thought
could arise from the operation of a machine like a computer or a human body.
The book’s thesis is that thought is the execution of a computer program
encoded in the DNA, that understanding is a consequence of the compact
structure of this program (which was achieved by evolution), and that this
program (and the thinking that it gives rise to) is meaningful because it
captures the underlying structure of the world.

The book provides relatively accessible
introductions to many important topics in computer science, mathematics,
molecular biology and other disciplines, including: gene transcription and
expression, neural networks, Bayesian statistics, information and communication
theory, genetic algorithms, learning theory, algorithmic complexity, and even
metaphor. It explains many highly technical concepts, including Turing
machines, the Vapnik-Chervonenkis dimension, Kholmogorov complexity, Bayes’
law, the Traveling Salesman Problem, and the class of NP-complete problems in
general. Anyone who has heard these terms but doesn’t know what they mean would
benefit from reading the relevant sections of this book. The technical
explanations are by and large clear, if sometimes incomplete. Nevertheless,
each explanation includes citations to the original literature on the topic,
allowing the reader who is sufficiently interested and motivated to follow up
on any topic. Many of the explanations assume some mathematical sophistication
(at least logarithms, summation notation, Boolean logic, and set theory). The
sorts of topics that What is Thought? addresses are similar to those in
Douglas Hofstadter’s books, especially Gödel, Escher, Bach, although
this book does not have quite the same flair as that one.

One of the central claims of this book–that
meaning comes from compression–is counter-intuitive. The book claims that
"If one compresses enough data into a small representation, the
representation captures…real meaning about the world" (102). But think
about the program WinZip, which compresses files on personal computers into
smaller packages that can be downloaded from websites or sent via email. Many
people are familiar with "Zip files," but nobody thinks that WinZip
has captured any real meaning about even the files on which it operates, let
alone about the world at large. Baum would presumably argue that this program
does not compress a wide enough spectrum of information into a small enough
representation. But what reason is there to think that a "SuperWinZip"
program that compressed more things better than regular WinZip would achieve
understanding? What is Thought? does not offer an answer.

What is Thought? frequently uses
anthropomorphic, teleological and intentional language to describe evolution:
"the DNA discovered how to build multicelled creatures" (311),
"evolution cannot find a use for computing an intermediate result until it
knows how to use it, and it can’t figure out how to use it until it knows how
to compute it" (323), "evolution has learned to learn" (323),
and "what evolution did … was to design the language" (340,
emphasis in the original). I assume that these claims are only offered as a
manner of speaking, that Baum does not seriously believe that DNA can discover
things, or that evolution can learn or design, strictly speaking.

The book also makes very strong innateness
claims. For example, Baum writes, "following the consensus view of the
linguistics community, I argue that we are specifically evolved to learn
language" (306). This view is emphatically not the consensus view of the
linguistics community, as a glance at a book on cognitive or functional
linguistics will verify–Michael Tomasello’s Constructing a Language is
a good, fairly accessible example. According to What is Thought?, not
only language and vision, but also social interaction, reasoning, and faculties
for understanding Euclidean space and causality, among other things, are
innate. Indeed, the book claims, "much of human concept structure is
biased in" (329). However, it is not clear exactly what it means mean for
something to be "innate." Throughout What is Thought?, one
gets the impression that just about anything can be "coded into,"
"programmed in," "wired into" or "built in to"
the genome, and this notion of coding seems to amount to a kind of physical
containment. Indeed, the book even contains passages about "putting"
and "pushing" knowledge into the genome (e.g., "it is not always
fitter to put knowledge into the genome" and "knowledge pushed into
the genome is there from birth" (333)). The same may be said about the
concept of a "bias." What is Thought? makes a good case that
some sort of inductive bias is necessary to get learning started in any sort of
system, be it human or computer. Rather than viewing such biases merely as
dispositions to behave (or change one’s behavior) in certain ways, however, the
book asserts that they are "in" the learner. Thus, we find statements
like "much learning in animals and presumably in people as well, including
language learning, is not general-purpose but specifically biased in"
(328). One wants to know: what exactly is "biased in" to what, and what
does this mean? For example, when we read that "animal learning is, to a
point, highly biased in, providing evidence for the innateness of much
learning" (347), are we supposed to conclude that "learning" is
somehow "in" the animal or "in" its DNA? If so, what is the
meaning of that claim? (Could we identify the location where the learning is,
for example by putting our finger on it?) If not, then why not merely say that
learning is biased instead of "biased in"?

What is Thought? argues that the mind
should be modular because modularity is good engineering practice (215). This
is a surprising argument in a book that is at pains elsewhere to point out that
engineering is not always the best way to solve a problem. Furthermore, the
concept of a "module" remains unanalyzed, although the book sometimes
suggests that modules are physiologically discrete brain structures: "it
seems plausible that the modules would be associated with different small
regions of the brain, each predisposed to learn or code different concepts"
(329). This is an unusual view–even those who agree that mind is modular
usually argue that the modularity is functional, not physiological.

It is nice to see someone from another
discipline taking philosophical issues seriously, and Baum has clearly taken
the time to read a substantial portion of the philosophical literature that is
relevant to his topic. However, the book contains some philosophical mistakes.
For instance, it asserts that cup is a natural kind (288). In fact, cup
is often used in philosophical discourse as an example of just the sort of
thing that is not a natural kind, that is, not the sort of thing that
enters into the laws of science.

What is Thought? grapples seriously with
hard issues about consciousness. To some extent, the conclusion is that
consciousness is an illusion (228, 385), but the book also analyzes
consciousness as consisting of several different faculties–including agency,
awareness, and qualitative experience–and treats them individually. The
conclusion that "awareness is simply our ability to talk about our summary
of the world and direct our computational abilities against portions of
it" (423) is reminiscent of Dennett’s in Consciousness Explained, a
debt that Baum explicitly acknowledges. The explanation of the qualitative aspects
of experience, on the other hand, is that they have to have the
phenomenological properties that they do. Pain, for example, is a "raw
penalty" and "intense hurt is precisely the experience we should
expect" given that that is its nature (424). I have to admit that I don’t
follow this argument. It is clear (a) that the "penalty" message is
important, and (b) that the ensuing behavior, such as withdrawal and future
avoidance, is important. But why should we expect, a priori, that the
pain should feel the way that it does? Why couldn’t some other sensation have
both communicated the appropriate message and caused the ensuing behavior? And
why is it necessary for the message or the cause to be associated with a
sensation at all?

According to What is Thought?, free will
is also an illusion. Consistent with his background as a computer scientist,
Baum frames the question of free will in terms of how it might be possible for
people to create wholly new mathematical axioms, something computer programs
cannot do. The book’s position is that people actually do not create wholly new
mathematical axioms–the axioms are innate. As Baum writes, "the mind is
created by execution of the DNA program, so the new axioms must have been
inherent in the DNA program…any ‘new’ axioms we generate can be derived from
this stored information and thus do not represent genuinely new bits of
information" (429-430). This is an old idea–one whose roots reach at
least as far back as Plato’s claim that knowledge is not acquired, merely
recollected–but it is implausible on the face of it. According to What is
Thought?
, the idea of free will (among other things, the intuition that
"new" axioms really are new) is just another computational module,
one that is convenient to adapt in order to efficiently explain behavior, both
others’ and one’s own.

All in all, this is an interesting book with
some intriguing ideas, but it does not quite find its niche. Attempts to
provide commonsense explanations of abstruse topics in the theory of computation
are welcome, and a willingness to struggle with hard philosophical questions is
noteworthy and commendable. On the other hand, the explanations and arguments
are not clear and simple enough for a truly popular audience, nor are they
rigorous and complete enough for specialists. In the end, no reader is likely
to be convinced by this book that thought is computation, that understanding is
compression, that most of our concepts are innate, or that both free will and
consciousness are nothing more than illusions.

 

 

 

© 2004 Aarre Laakso

 

 

Aarre Laakso received his Ph.D. in Philosophy
and Cognitive Science from UC San Diego. He is currently a postdoctoral
researcher in the Psychology Department at Indiana University, Bloomington.

Categories: Philosophical, Psychology